Skip to content
Οἱ δέ, ἰδόντες αὐτὸν περιπατοῦντα ἐπὶ τῆς θαλάσσης, ἔδοξαν φάντασμα εἶναι, καὶ ἀνέκραξαν·
RBT Greek Interlinear:
Strongs 3588  [list]
Λογεῖον
Perseus
hoi
οἱ
the
Art-NMP
Strongs 1161  [list]
Λογεῖον
Perseus
de
δὲ
and
Conj
Strongs 3708  [list]
Λογεῖον
Perseus
idontes
ἰδόντες
those who have perceived
V-APA-NMP
Strongs 846  [list]
Λογεῖον
Perseus
auton
αὐτὸν
himself
PPro-AM3S
Strongs 1909  [list]
Λογεῖον
Perseus
epi
ἐπὶ
upon
Prep
Strongs 3588  [list]
Λογεῖον
Perseus
tēs
τῆς
the
Art-GFS
Strongs 2281  [list]
Λογεῖον
Perseus
thalassēs
θαλάσσης
sea
N-GFS
Strongs 4043  [list]
Λογεῖον
Perseus
peripatounta
περιπατοῦντα
he who is walking
V-PPA-AMS
Strongs 1380  [list]
Λογεῖον
Perseus
edoxan
ἔδοξαν
thought
V-AIA-3P
Strongs 3754  [list]
Λογεῖον
Perseus
hoti
ὅτι
that
Conj
Strongs 5326  [list]
Λογεῖον
Perseus
phantasma
φάντασμά
a ghost
N-NNS
Strongs 1510  [list]
Λογεῖον
Perseus
estin
ἐστιν
is
V-PIA-3S
Strongs 2532  [list]
Λογεῖον
Perseus
kai
καὶ
and
Conj
Strongs 349  [list]
Λογεῖον
Perseus
anekraxan
ἀνέκραξαν
cried out
V-AIA-3P
RBT Translation:
φάντασμα Phantasma - Mental Image, visionary experience
And the ones who have perceived himself on the Sea, he who is walking, they believed that he is a phantasma,19 and they cried up.
LITV Translation:
But seeing Him walking on the sea, they thought it to be a ghost. And they cried out.
ESV Translation:
Error retrieving verse.

Footnotes

19

Phantasma

φάντασμα, -ατος (τὸ): Refers to various types of appearances or phenomena, including: 1) an apparition, vision, or dream (Plato, Republic 510a; Theocritus, Idylls 21.30); 2) a mental image or representation formed by an object or thought, often implying insubstantiality (Plato, Phaedo 81d; Aristotle, De Anima 3.3.9); 3) a specter or ghost, typically a supernatural apparition (Aeschylus, Seven Against Thebes 710; Euripides, Hecuba 54, 95, 390; Plato, Phaedo 81d, Timaeus 71a); 4) a celestial phenomenon or extraordinary event (Aristotle, De Mundo 4.21; Dionysius of Halicarnassus, 4.62; Plutarch, Dion 2). Derived from φαντάζω (phantazo), meaning "to make visible" or "to appear."

In philosophical contexts, the word φάντασμα (phantasma) was used to describe mental images or appearances that arise in the mind, often as a result of sensory perception, imagination, or reasoning. These images or phenomena are not necessarily linked to physical reality but are the products of the mind's activity. The term was used by philosophers like Plato and Aristotle to explore concepts of perception, reality, and knowledge.

  1. Plato:

    • In his dialogues, φάντασμα is often used to describe mental images or appearances that arise from the interaction between the mind and the external world. Plato viewed these appearances as insubstantial and unreliable, in contrast to the true knowledge found in the realm of the Forms.
      • For example, in Phaedo (81d), Plato discusses how physical appearances (which are mere φάσματα) can deceive us, as they are only reflections or shadows of the true, unchanging reality of the Forms.
      • In Parmenides (166a), he uses the term to indicate the illusory nature of appearances in the material world, which can give us false beliefs about reality.
  2. Aristotle:

    • Aristotle, in works like the De Anima (On the Soul), also discusses φάντασμα as mental images that are produced by the interaction of the soul with external stimuli. These images are the mind’s representations of the sensory input it receives.
    • He saw these mental images as crucial to human cognition, but he differentiated between phantasms (which arise from sense perception) and actual knowledge (which arises from reason and intellectual understanding).
      • For example, in De Anima (3.3.9), Aristotle argues that these images or phantasms are important in the process of memory and imagination, but they are not equivalent to true knowledge.
  3. Epistemological Implications:

    • In both Plato and Aristotle's philosophies, φάντασμα highlights the tension between appearance and reality. Philosophers used the concept to explore whether the images and appearances presented by the senses are trustworthy sources of knowledge or if they merely veil the truth.
    • Plato, especially, emphasized that sensory experiences and their corresponding mental images (i.e., φάσματα) were deceptive, leading to ignorance if relied upon too heavily. He believed that true knowledge comes from reasoning about the Forms, not from the imperfect, changing world of appearances.
    • Aristotle, while recognizing the importance of sensory images in knowledge formation, also distinguished between appearances and scientific knowledge, advocating that while our senses provide us with useful information, true knowledge comes from abstract reasoning.